Note: The following article was published in 2004 in The Record (a Kitchener-Waterloo newspaper) and I post
it here to make it available to interested readers. The article was the 2005
winner of the General Readership category (newspaper article) awarded by The Word
Guild.
A scene from the 2004 film The Passion of The Christ, directed by Mel Gibson |
Did the Easter
miracle happen?
By Hendrik van der
Breggen
The Record, April 10, 2004
Think
of Easter and immediately bunnies and coloured eggs come to mind. However, as
Mel Gibson's film The Passion of the
Christ has reminded us, Easter has more to do with Jesus and the Christian
gospel than it has to do with chocolate.
The traditional Christian
gospel or good news is that God (God the Son) came to Earth in the man Jesus,
He took our punishment for sin onto Himself by suffering and dying on a cross,
and then God (the Father) raised Jesus from the grave (tomb). Jesus'
resurrection, that is His return to life in the same body but somehow
wonderfully renewed, is said to be a glorious sign to help us believe—accept by
faith—the good news.
Of course, this begs the
question: Is it reasonable to believe that Jesus actually resurrected?
In the little book The Case for Easter: A Journalist
Investigates the Evidence for the Resurrection (Zondervan 2003), former
journalist and former spiritual skeptic Lee Strobel argues that, yes, it is
reasonable to believe that Jesus actually resurrected.
Strobel makes his case
for Jesus' resurrection by appealing to, and defending, three historical facts:
○ Jesus was actually killed by crucifixion;
○ The tomb in which Jesus' dead body was placed was
found empty a couple days later;
○ And Jesus was subsequently seen alive and well for
several weeks in various locations, not only by a skeptic who touched Him to
make sure He wasn't a ghost, but also by other individuals and variously sized
groups of people, many of whom engaged Jesus in conversation and had meals with
Him—and would later endure torture and death rather than recant their
testimony.
THERE ARE OTHER
EXPLANATIONS
Strobel also considers
alternative, non-resurrection explanations—such as Jesus didn't really die, the
witnesses hallucinated, a conspiracy occurred or it's all legend—but argues
that they are all weak. Strobel's arguments are, I believe, strong, but because
of space limitations I won't discuss those arguments here. I recommend that
anyone who is interested in the problems with the non-miracle theories check
out Strobel's book.
What I find interesting
is that the alternative non-resurrection explanations, even the most outlandish
ones which haven't a shred of evidence in their favour, such as Jesus has an
unknown twin who pretended to be the resurrected Jesus after Jesus died, tend
to be set forth by many—and clung to—primarily because of a philosophical
reason.
How so? The proponents of
the far-fetched have been infected by a skeptical philosophical view that has
been transmitted to us from the Scottish philosopher David Hume.
If your son or daughter
goes to university today and takes an introductory philosophy class, he or she
will probably run into David Hume. Well, not David Hume in person, but a
philosophy professor who is a kindred spirit.
Hume lived from 1711 to
1776. He is famous, rather notorious, for, among, other things, his argument
against miracles. According to Hume, no matter how good the historical evidence
is for a miracle such as Jesus' resurrection—even if the miracle actually
occurred—the evidence is never good enough.
Hume argues that a
miracle is a violation of a law of nature and that the laws of nature are very
well established. The result, according to Hume, is that a miracle's occurrence
is maximally improbable, and this maximal improbability counts against any good
testimony for a miracle, either balancing the testimony (thereby providing
grounds to suspend belief) or outweighing it (thereby providing grounds for
disbelief). In reality, Hume thinks the latter is the case. Either way, though,
Hume would have us dismiss miracle testimonies as unreasonable to believe.
CIRCULAR REASONING
Having studied Hume's
argument for my master's thesis in philosophy at the University of Windsor and
for my PhD dissertation in philosophy at the University of Waterloo, I have
come to conclude that Hume's argument fails.
His argument fails
because it begs the question. It “begs the question” in the sense that it engages in circular reasoning,
it assumes as proven that which is at issue, and it sneaks the conclusion into
the premises.
As mentioned, Hume takes
the violation-of-law-of-nature aspect of a miracle to be sufficient grounds for
counting the violated laws of nature wholly and destructively against miracle
testimony—to judge the miracle to be maximally improbable.
Interestingly, in the
case of Jesus' resurrection, such an event is maximally improbable, given the
laws of nature and given that there is no intervention from outside the
physical system. Significantly, this brings to light the fact that Hume makes
the assumption that to make a probability judgment all that is needed is our
knowledge of the relevant laws of nature.
But, it should be
emphasized, we are supposedly talking about a miraculous resurrection (as
suggested by the evidence), and so, although we are given the laws of nature,
we are not given that there is no intervention from outside the system.
So in assuming that all
that is needed is our knowledge of the relevant laws of nature and nothing
about any possible intervention from outside of nature, Hume is, in effect,
assuming that either God does not exist (and so God never intervenes via
miracles) or, if God does exist, God's intentions concerning nature are shown
to us wholly by the laws of nature (and so God never intervenes via miracles).
But if, as Hume assumes
for the sake of argument, there is good evidence for what seems very much to be
a miracle—Hume even allows it to be a real miracle—then Hume's assumption about
the background knowledge is at issue.
In other words, in order
for Hume's argument to work, it requires the assumption that the laws of nature
express either all the goings-on of a universe without God or, if God exists,
all of God's intentions concerning the universe. But the truth of this
assumption must be put on hold when a miracle (whether actual or alleged) is
supposed to be under investigation.
Indeed, for one's mind to
be actually open to the possibility of the occurrence of an occasional real
miracle—a possibility Hume allows, at least for the sake of argument—requires
that the assumption Hume makes be suspended—at least when one is purportedly
investigating the evidence for a miracle.
In other words, Hume's
argument works only if we assume that there is no God who on rare occasions
intervenes in nature, but this assumption is at issue when we are considering
any alleged evidence for miracles.
LOOK AT THE EVIDENCE
Thus, by assuming the
above-described background knowledge, Hume mistakenly begs the question which
only the (alleged) miracle evidence can answer.
Hume's mind is already
made up then, and not open to what the evidence suggests.
The upshot is that if
your mind is not already closed to the possibility of a God who occasionally
does a miracle, that is, if your mind is open to the possibility of God's
existence and the possibility of this God intervening in nature, then the facts
surrounding Jesus' alleged resurrection may make a miraculous resurrection
explanation plausible, and even reasonable to believe.
If you weren't a believer
in the past, Easter might now take on a whole new meaning.
Postscript (September 17, 2016): The notion of God “intervening” in
nature can also be understood as God engaging in a special act vis-à-vis God's ongoing act of sustaining the creation. Space limitations in a newspaper
article are not conducive to adding philosophical-theological nuance.
----
Hendrik van der Breggen, PhD, is associate professor of philosophy at Providence University College.
No comments:
Post a Comment